

Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
John dewey explores the debate on whether significant innate differences between males and females influence their success in science. He discusses pinker and russett's perspectives on the role of biology and socialization in shaping gender differences. Dewey argues that both nature and nurture contribute to development, but finds pinker's arguments for a more influential role of biology unconvincing.
Typology: Study notes
1 / 2
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
John Dewey, PSY 360
Do Significant Innate Differences Influence the Success of Males and Females?
Are male and female brains so genetically distinct that the differences account for specific developmental outcomes? There seem to be two levels to this issue—one is about actual cognitive abilities, and the other is about how to discuss group differences. In regard to cognitive abilities, it does seem likely that there are sex differences in cognitive ability—some of which favor men and some of which favor women. But, in regard to discussing group differences, it does not seem likely that discussing those differences as causing specific developmental outcomes is valid. Thus, my initial position is no: significant innate differences do not influence the success of males and females.
In the readings on this issue Pinker notes three possible explanations for the fact that only 20% of scientists in “hard science” disciplines are women, the second of which “is that gender disparities can arise in the absence of discrimination as long as men and women differ, on average, in their mixture of talents, temperaments, and interests—whether this difference is the result of biology, socialization, or an interaction of the two” (p. 52). Although Pinker groups nature and nurture together as one explanation, this seems to be the key question in relation to lifespan development: do women differ from men on average primarily because of socialization or primarily because of biology? As noted in class, our development is always a product of an interaction between nature and nurture. So it is not a question of either/or – but rather which is more influential.
Pinker implies that nature is more influential. To me, however, his arguments were unconvincing. He argues that sex differences are real, and based on genetic differences (though he does acknowledge the differences do not necessarily favor men or women—in some cases depending on society they may favor either). He uses evolutionary speculation to explain these differences, arguing that reproduction requires different characteristics from men and women. But these speculations sound like the “just so stories” those critical of evolutionary psychology deride. Pinker, for example, claims that in families having one really smart son can outweigh “dull sons” more than having one really smart daughter. This seems to be ungrounded evolutionary speculation.
In contrast, Russett implies that society is more influential in determining the meaning of sex differences. She points out that biological differences are easy to misinterpret. For example, men do, on average, have bigger brains than women, but they also have more body mass and proportionately their brains are not in fact larger. She points to a pattern of misleading thinking through history that clearly demonstrates how our theories are dictated by our society.
Yet, as both Pinker and our text point out, efforts to raise children of different sexes without regard to gender have not diminished the salience of gender in society. In fact, most efforts to “re-assign” gender through socialization have failed. It does seem that gender differences have an innate developmental root. In fact, in the text the discussion of genetic bases for our development notes that we have many “sex-linked traits.” These are traits that are linked specifically to the x or y chromosome, and mostly determine things such as blood type or eye color. It is, of course, a grand leap to say that these “sex-linked” traits also influence later life abilities in science. There is too much socialization in-between. But if sex differences are inscribed at the most basic genetic level, it seems necessary to admit that some gender differences must have a genetic basis.
At the same time, the manifestation of those traits depends heavily on society and culture. As the text also notes, even identical twins (who share identical genetic material) do not develop with absolutely identical psychological characteristics. Genes are never destiny. Ultimately, Laurence Summers and Pinker rely on the notion that the top end of the curve for cognitive abilities related to science is dominated by men (they cite a ratio of 5:1). The problem with this logic is that it assumes top scientists are simply the innately smartest people. Even for men, if they are not provided the education, resources, and opportunities to succeed in science they will not succeed. In lifespan development, our genetic dispositions provide a broad foundation for who we become, but the actual direction we take is too heavily influenced by society to think that accounting for innate sex differences would help us constructively understand something as particular as gender disparities in science.
Two questions that would be useful to discuss in relation to this issue are: